Davies—Works of Music

Works of Music: Approaches to the Ontology of Music from Analytic Philosophy

Stephen Davies

Abstract: In this article, I interrogate the issues and philosophical theories about the ontological character of musical works presented by analytic philosophers over the past forty years. The focus is on Western art music, but jazz and popular music are also discussed. I recognize the historical plasticity of the notion of works of music. I distinguish playings that are not of works (such as improvisations) from work performances, works for playback from works for live performance, and works recorded from live performances. I question the current fashion of applying theories of personhood (personal identity) to the musical case, arguing that these face more problems than they solve. And, as well as reviewing the many theories on show and their metaphysical presumptions, I defend the enterprise of ontological analysis against skepticism about its worth, arguing for its relevance to assessments of musical value and to performance practices. Ultimately, I defend a descriptivist ontology (one that attempts to track ordinary discourse about musical works), a contextualist analysis (one that acknowledges how relations between the work and its musico-historical context can affect its constitutive properties), and an approach that treats musical works as concrete and present in the world, rather than as abstract items or as non-existent.

Keywords: ontology, musical work, performance, analytic philosophy

Steven Davies is Distinguished Professor of Philosophy at the University of Auckland.

Davies, Stephen. 2020. “Works of Music: Approaches to the Ontology of Music from Analytic Philosophy.” Music Research Annual 1: 1–29. ISSN 2563-7290

PDF version of this article | Table of contents for this volume

In this article, I interrogate the issues and philosophical theories about musical works presented by analytic philosophers over the past forty years. Ontology is concerned with the nature of things or the manner in which they exist. Thus, our topic is the ontological analysis of musical works; it is about what kinds of things they are. Such enquiries have their own, intrinsic interest, but they have important practical implications as well. Plainly, we cannot characterize the relation between works and the performances of them if we have no understanding of what musical works are. And how we answer that question will have implications for what can be expected or even required from performers who attempt to play such works. For example, whether we think historically-informed performance is an optional interpretative possibility or, instead, is something more strictly required in a performance that advertises itself as of a given work, depends in part on what we judge to be constitutive of that or similar works. To anticipate one important conclusion that will follow: Musical works are not ontologically homogenous; they come in different grades and types.

Analytic philosophy is usually committed to the clear (but sometimes technical) presentation and analysis of arguments and issues. Methodology in this area of philosophy is typically dialogical, with competing theories played off against each other by their critics and proponents.

By contrast, philosophy in the Continental style is sometimes more concerned with personal experiences and values than publicly-shared ones, and with all-embracing, wide-ranging theories rather than isolated topics. Some Continental philosophers, such as Roman Ingarden (1968), have addressed the ontology of music, but their writings lie beyond the deliberately restricted scope of this article.

The Work Concept Used Here

By work of music I mean a repeatable sonic entity the identity of which persists over its repetitions; it is the same work each time. Frequently, such works are named, such as Fireworks, or are otherwise specified, for example, Sonata for Piano, Opus 20.

The soundings of such works in some cases involve performances, either live or in a studio, where they are recorded. In others, they involve playbacks of electronic files (or of other encodings of the work, such as vinyl disks, music boxes, mechanical organs, pianola rolls). The creation of such files need not involve performance, that is, the sounding forth of music from the body or from musical instruments or other resonators. Some works, such as Beethoven’s Symphony No. 5, are for performance. Others, such as Edgar Varése’s Poème Électronique (1957–58) are for playback. And some works combine both options, such as Luigi Nono’s La Fabbrica Illuminata (1964), which is for soprano and tape.

Some people reserve the term musical work for sustained pieces with detailed, rigidly specified features, so the works are quite similar from performance to performance. This sometimes goes with the view that no musical works existed prior to the nineteenth century (Goehr 1992). Alongside this, a contrast might be drawn between, on the one hand, music as activity, skill, and know-how and, on the other, music as a collection of works of art. The latter perspective, which valorizes composers above performers, is seen in the Western art music tradition as modern and as contrasting with earlier traditions that emphasized the idea of music as a practice rather than as a succession of works.  As philosopher Patricia Carpenter has observed, “In our contemporary way of thinking, a piece of music is a specific kind of an object…ultimately, an object made for its own sake, a form of being-in-itself. On this view, ‘music,’ then, becomes the total collection of all its pieces, the imaginary museum of musical works” (Carpenter 1967, 68).

I see no reason to privilege extended, highly specified Western works in this way and prefer more relaxed conditions for work identity (S. Davies 2001, 2003). For my purposes, “Happy Birthday” (the melody of which comes from “Good Morning to All,” attributed to Patty and Mildred Hill, c. 1893) is a musical work. It can have many renditions and, despite how these differ (e.g., in whose name is sung), each is identifiable as being of the same piece. Indeed, in my view, works are ancient and present in almost all musical cultures. “Sumer is icumen in” is a mid-thirteenth-century work in my view. Other musical works are the Nepalese folk song “Chura ta Hoina Astura,” the Balinese piece “Teruna jaya” (which was composed by Gedé Manik and dates in its earliest version to about 1918), Robert Johnson’s Mississippi delta blues known as “Cross Road Blues,” the traditional Shona (Zimbabwe) song “Mahororo” with mbira accompaniment, “Moon of my Hometown” composed by Byungki Hwang for voice, the Korean gayageum and janggu, and on and on. Finally, neither do I see an interest in works as thereby denigrating a process-oriented notion of music as practice. We can be interested in works, the process of realizing them, and in freer musical events not at all work-focused.

Musical Playings Not of Works

Let’s emphasize this last point before proceeding. Not all musical playings are of works. Music can be freely improvised, a practice that is central to some forms of jazz and to many Indigenous music-and-dance traditions. (In a few musical cultures, there might be no works, though I believe such cultures would be a small minority.) In jazz, sometimes such improvising begins with an identifiable thematic kernel, the head, that inspires the musicians’ ideas. What happens is not a performance of a piece identified with that tune but a free work after or inspired by it. (For this view, see S. Davies 2001; Kania 2011.) In other cases, the improvisation is deliberately more constrained, for example, by following the initial chord sequence, but again it is not obvious that that should identify what is done as work-performance. This is not to deny there might be some repeatable works in the jazz tradition (see Young and Matheson 2000), but it rejects the view (defended in Dodd 2014) that this is the paradigm. (For attempts to find a middle ground, see Brown, Goldblatt, and Gracyk 2018 and Fisher 2018.)

Other examples of musical playings that are not of works would be the output of a device that generates tones according to a randomizing algorithm and some musical exercises, such as scales, arpeggios, and similar configurations.

The Historical Plasticity of Musical Works

Though I have rejected the view that musical works emerged at a specific historic moment, it is important to acknowledge the flexibility of the work notion.

Where composers controlled the resources at their disposal (for instance, the musical instruments available to play their works) and the staging conditions of renditions of their works, they could invest those works with a fair amount of constitutive detail. What is more, even in oral traditions, it is possible to export works of some detail and complexity across the musical landscape. Where there is extensive training and mnemonic notations or devices, as in Catholic chant traditions, work fidelity was preserved over geographical and temporal spreads (Apel 1958 and Grout 2010). Alternatively, where the melodic or harmonic spine of the work is relatively simple, and decorating instruments derive their parts from this in a systematic (if also creative) fashion as is the case with central Javanese gamelan, extended works retain their identity over different renditions.

Nevertheless, over the course of Western music history, there has been a tendency for works to become specified in more detail over time. This went hand-in-hand with changes in the practices of music-making and presentation: standardization of instruments, increased proficiency and professionalism within guilds of musicians, solidification of performance practices and conventions regarding presentations of works and concert behavior, and gradual increase in the size of the instrumental ensemble (with a corresponding increase in difficulty in co-ordinating the group), with this last leading to the development of more complex instrument-specific and generic notations, and so on. These changes made it increasingly possible for composers to be confident the details and complexities of their works would be faithfully reproduced wherever the work was played, which of course led to the increasing complexity and extension of those works.

I distinguish thin from thick musical works (S. Davies 1991, 2001). “Happy Birthday” is thin. In this case, the work consists only of the melody and implied harmonic structure (and words, in sung versions). It could be played in any number of arrangements on all kinds of instruments. Many Tin Pan Alley songs are comparatively thin, as their sheet music implies by showing only words, sung melody, and chord tablatures. Thin works allow more latitude to the performer, often regarding structure, instrumentation, embellishment, tempo, dynamics, and phrasing.

By comparison, a Mahler symphony is thick with work-constitutive properties including its instrumentation, phrasing, dynamics, and so forth. The thicker the work, the more constrained is the performer in playing it accurately and the more the features of an accurate performance are attributable to the work, rather than to the performer’s interpretation of it. (That said, even the most heavily-specified work for live performance leaves a great deal to the interpretation of the performer. See Godlovitch 1988 and Thom 2007.) So, we can characterize the long-term historical tendency noted above for Western art music by describing it as one in which works became progressively thicker.

As I use it, the thick/thin distinction makes no implicit judgment about work quality. By comparison with nineteenth-century Romantic music, most Medieval and Renaissance music is thin but, of course, not inferior on that account. The thickening of musical works is not tantamount to a kind of progress by which they become better. The distinction is relevant only to assigning responsibility for which aspects of a fully replete performance’s sounding belong to the work and which aspects to the performer’s rendition.

The thickening of musical works went hand-in-hand with developments in notations and scores, with composers indicating with more and more specificity what the performer was supposed to bring off. In the twentieth-century, there was something of a reaction to this kind of musical determinism. Composers adopted (or instructed) aleatoric methods or chance procedures for determining the work’s content. Provided the chance procedure generated a specific outcome, the result was not a thinning of the work. Responsibility for the outcome shifted, however, from the composer, who no longer controlled the selection of notes, to the non-deterministic procedure.

An Aside on Scores

Most work-specifying scores should be regarded as sets of instructions addressed to performers (S. Davies 1987, 1991, 2001; Thom 2003, 2007): If you would perform my work, do thus and so! As I have observed, complex, extended works can be preserved within oral traditions, but the adoption of notations increases the opportunities for creating large-scale orchestral and choral works.

Not all musical notations are scores of this kind, however. Some, for example, are transcriptions of performances or mnemonics for work renditions. Others notate what is produced by a mechanical sound generator, such as a music box, not by a performer. Others offer pictorial renditions of purely electronic works.

The case in which the composer instructs the performer not on the notes to be played but on some procedure—perhaps including random elements—for generating the work’s content, as was just mentioned previously, raises another question. We might wonder whether we are getting a score for a work that can have many very different performance realizations or, instead, a composition manual for generating many different works.

In some cases, the answer might be clear from what we get. Mozart’s Musikalische Würfel Spiel (S. Davies 2001, 109) provides a kit for composing minuets, not a work score. In other cases, the answer might not be obvious nor how we answer important.

The Work in Rock

A graphic illustration of the plasticity of the work notion is apparent in the complex relation between audio technologies and popular music. Writing in the 1990s, Theodore Gracyck (1996) made a strong case for regarding the primary work in rock as the recorded track and, in some cases, above that, the album. Concept albums were thematized and presented as wholes rather than as lists of tracks. Opponents suggested instead that rock is primarily a performance tradition (see Baugh 1993); or, at least, performance is no less important than recording (see Burkett 2015 and Bartel 2017); or the primary work is the song, rather than the recording (see Bruno 2013). Of course, the CD quickly overtook the vinyl record, and some years later Andrew Kania thought the primary work was (again) the (now digital) track (2006, 2008b; see also Fisher 1998 and Luzio 2019).

But unified collections of tracks had become less common by that time. Nowadays, the primary work is a song, understood as an electronic file, probably streamed, though clearly related to the digital track formerly found on a CD. These are collected into playlists personal to the listener, and the notion of the album has become much less prominent. Changes in how people access and listen to their music, which are a function of changes in audio technologies, thus may have altered how we think about the ontology of the primary items of musical appreciation in the popular music tradition.

Skepticism About the Enterprise

Some philosophers have questioned the value of doing musical metaphysics and quite a few musicologists regard the enterprise as so abstract and arcane that it is irrelevant to the real-world practice of playing music. Philosopher Aaron Ridley, for instance, suggests that folk (that is, common-sense) intuitions about the identity of musical works and the performances of them suffice, so arguments about ontology are irrelevant and unhelpful, while leading to the neglect of what really matters: the critical evaluation of work renditions (Ridley 2003). (For other reservations and discussion, see Bartel 2011, Kraut 2012, Young 2014–15.) Furthermore, Ridley questions what he sees as the obsession with authenticity or fidelity in performances that is a consequence of the interest in ontology, when what should concern us, he believes, is the quality of performance more generally (Ridley 2003). When it comes to my trying ineptly to play Bach on an electric keyboard, questions of authenticity are quite irrelevant to what I’m trying to do and to what motivates me. And something similar might be thought to apply in the professional realm to those who mistake a literalist focus on historical practices for genuine interpretative insight. I’ll take up this issue below.

A more modest doubt is expressed by Lee B. Brown about what he calls “higher-order musical ontologies” that ask of broad genres (such as rock, jazz, and Western art music) what primary form the work takes in each (Brown 2011, 2012). (For examples of such theorizing, see Kania 2006, 2008a, 2011. The previous discussions of rock and jazz in this article also concerned higher-order ontology.) Within each of these higher-order categories, the variety of kinds of works is striking and no single kind is primary, Brown thinks.

Andrew Kania has defended the philosophical enterprise of music ontology against these concerns (Kania 2008b, 2012a). Ontological arguments have their own value and, as well, can sometimes be relevant to the judgments of musical value that interest Ridley. And, provided they aim to be descriptive, they should respect and accommodate differences between kinds of musical works. I would add this: It’s far from obvious that we all coincide in or should rely on our folk intuitions about musical works, or that we are always aware of their implications. Many of the issues and controversies surrounding the nature of performance and how performances stand in relation to works could be approached more perspicuously with the aid of ontologies sensitive to musical practices (and their historical contingencies). Not all ontological debates are interesting in this way, but some can be.

In addition, ontology is always at risk of being converted into ideology, implicitly arguing that some types of works, compositional practices, or styles of music are superior to others, and this should be avoided (see Sharpe 2000). But that seems more rife among musicologists, who mix sociological, political, and psychological concerns more readily with ontological questions than do analytic philosophers. Important questions can be asked about the artistic and moral comparisons that can be made between different musical works or musical kinds, and about who if anyone is entitled to make them, but the ontological enterprise can and should operate independently of these judgments about value.

Revisionary Versus Descriptivist Metaphysics

One reason why musicologists are irritated by musical ontologists is because some of the latter are revisionists (a.k.a. prescriptivists) rather than descriptivists. They think philosophical categories and arguments are more secure than folk intuitions and are thereby comfortable developing theories of the musical work that plainly contradict common-sense notions about such things. (For instance, see Goodman 1968 and Dodd 2007.) Some revisionists (such as Rudner 1950) actually want to reform ordinary talk to conform to their theories but others (such as Goodman 1968) do not. By contrast, descriptivists expect the appropriate ontologies to track ordinary talk about musical works and judge them by how well they do so.

Here are some examples of revisionist views: Nelson Goodman (1968) argues that the smallest departure from a work-specifying notation disqualifies a playing from being a performance of the work so specified. A rendition with a single wrong note fails to instance the work, according to him. His worry is that denying this opens up a slippery slope that reduces different pieces to a single work. In practice, however, musical people tolerate and expect errors in performance and other departures from the score, while accepting performances with such blemishes as being of the work in question. At the same time, Goodman rejects tempo indications, such as Allegro, as too vague to be work-specifying and thereby is committed to regarding a performance that takes years to execute as not deficient on that count. (For further criticisms of Goodman, see S. Davies 1991, 2001; Edlund 1996; and Predelli 1999.)

Meanwhile, Platonists (about whom more below) regard musical works as existing eternally and as discovered rather than created. They do so because they equate musical works with patterns of notes and regard patterns as abstract items that exist apart from their concrete instances. By contrast, musical folk think of musical works as coming into existence at more or less datable times and take works that once existed but of which all trace is now lost, such as Mozart’s Trumpet Concerto K. 47c, as non-existent, not merely as still existing though inaccessible.

Other revisionist views maintain musical works are ideas in the minds of composers (Cray and Matheson 2017) or, along with other works of art, that they are actions: either acts of discovering via a particular heuristic path the structure that is the work’s outward face (Currie 1988), or acts of creation (D. Davies 2003). Another view that flirts with revisionism is fictionalism, which holds there are no such things as musical works, but we talk as if there are for ease of reference in describing musical playings (Kania 2008c, 2012b; Killin 2017). Similarly counterintuitive is the position that maintains that the sentence “there are musical works” is true but there are no musical works (Cameron 2008; see also Letts 2018; for critical discussion, see Predelli 2009, Stecker 2009, and D. Davies 2018).

We can put the issue of revisionary versus descriptive metaphysics of music into perspective by placing it in the context of other kinds of ontological claims. It is clear, for example, that we could be mistaken about the fundamental nature of natural kinds such as the elements of the periodic table. Or we might think that whales are fish. And we can be deeply wrong about natural events, taking the earthquake to be a punishment for human transgressions. We can even be in error about the point of our social practices. Religion might be about establishing social cohesion and group identity and not at all about finding a route to an eternal Paradise, whatever the holy books say. But in the case of socially constructed kinds—money, the Stanley Cup, parking tickets, good germs, credit cards, and musical works—it seems implausible we could all be wrong all of the time about what they are. (Thus, we might be ignorant about how the nature of the economy affects the political system, say, but we could not all be wrong at the same time about what is legal tender.)

Ontological accounts of such items should, on the one hand, presume in favor of descriptivism, then. But on the other hand, we can be confused and inconsistent in our approach to the social world. Moreover, there can be cases in which several options seem equally plausible, yet considerations based in theory—consistency, economy, and so on—should lead us to opt for one over the others. So, a worked-out ontology might reasonably reject some of our folk classifications and intuitions, even if it should not challenge them all. A degree of revisionism should be tolerated, even if most of the time our ontologies should be consistent where possible with folk theories about the nature of social items, including musical works. (For further discussion of revisionism versus descriptivism, see D. Davies 2003, 2017; Thomasson 2005; Dodd 2007, 2013; Kania 2008c, 2012b; Stecker 2009; Neufeld 2014; and Killin 2017.)

Two Basic Kinds of Musical Works

I’ve already suggested that musical works come in two distinct varieties: those that are for playback, not performance, and those that are for live performance.

Let’s begin with works for playback. These often take the form of encodings cloned from a master and they are sounded when the encoding is decoded by an appropriate audio-output apparatus. For instance, a digital file is played by an industry-standard audio device under normal listening conditions, as when a recorded song is streamed through a computer or played on the radio. In the terminology introduced earlier, such musical works are thick in that almost all that is heard on playback is attributable to the work, there being no performance interpretation involved. Some of what is heard might not be attributable to the work, however. Tape hiss might be present in the file or the vinyl grooves might be poorly printed. And not every playback will sound exactly the same.  Playback devices might be differently equalized, distort, or fail to sound some of the information in the file—consider the difference in sound quality between earbuds and expensive speakers! But keeping such qualifications in mind, most of what is heard in a playback is the work itself.

Prior to the invention of recording technology such works were rare, but there were mechanical-sounding devices activated by such things as turning metal disks with holes, perforated moving paper sheets, turning metal barrels with prongs, and so on. Composers created musical works specifically for such devices. For instance, Mozart wrote an Adagio and Allegro in F minor, K. 594, for a mechanical organ and Stravinsky wrote an Étude for Pianola in 1917 as a demonstration piece for the player piano then produced by the Aeolian Company (The Pianola Institute 2019). Such pieces could be performed as well, though Stravinsky’s Étude would have required three pianos. (As it happened, it was later re-titled and orchestrated for live instrumental performance.)

Electronic musical works can be created on computers. Historically, studios in Cologne under the direction of Herbert Eimert played a leading role in the development of such music: Elektronische Musik. At the time, this was strongly distinguished from musique concrète, associated with Pierre Schaeffer, that used samples of recorded sounds as its primary source, editing and manipulating them in the studio. These sounds could be from nature or from the human, mechanized environment (but they were not specifically of musicians playing music). These days, the distinction between such ways of composing might not strike us as significant and, anyway, both lead to works that are for playback, not live performance.

One option, that of recording music played in the studio, became the preferred method in Western popular music (Gracyk 1996; Fisher 1998; Kania 2006, 2008a). Already from the 1950s, the works produced relied on interventions made in the studio: filters, multi-tracking, editing, tapes played faster or slower than the recording speed, and so forth. In other words, recordings in these cases deliberately created a mastered finish, rather than trying to emulate documentary-style recordings of live playings. Just as actors are involved in making movies, where the result is not a live performance but a work for playback (in this case, for screening), so musicians contribute to the work issued as a recording.

It should be noted that works for playback can sometimes be released in different but fairly similar versions. The original might be remixed or turned from mono to stereo, for instance, by a person with appropriate authority to release the result under the work’s name. Continuing the comparison with movies, this would be similar to the director’s cut. As long as versions are correctly dated and referenced, they needn’t cause philosophical angst. The world of musical works can be an untidy place.

I have described works of the kind we are discussing as “works for studio performance” (S. Davies 2001, 35). But this notion is perhaps already outdated to the extent that some studio effects can be applied in real time to live performances. For example, autotune corrects intonation, drum machines and foot-pedal devices introduce electronic percussion, auto harmony adds vocals, and pre-sampled effects can be played at the touch of a key. Meanwhile, with increased computational power and appropriate playback technologies, electronically-produced music can now be improvised in real time, as with the original rap DJs and groups such The Chemical Brothers. (For other criticisms of the distinction between live and studio performances, see Kania 2006, 2008a.)

These alterations certainly undermine what were previously clearly marked distinctions, such as between recorded and live music, and between electronically-produced and improvised music. A similar blurring occurs when works presented as recorded live in fact involve heavy studio editing. (Led Zeppelin’s “The Song Remains The Same” is a case in point.) Meanwhile, in popular music, the live performance sometimes rivals the recording in importance.

Nevertheless, we can still make the familiar distinctions by appealing to the sonic ideals invoked and the products issued. Improvised electronic music falls in the category of music making without works, unless it is recorded and issued as a piece (and also provided this recording is appropriately authorized, so it is not instead a bootleg recording of a live playing). Music released on disk, and that bears obvious marks of electronic production, represents works for playback, even if elements of live performances are included. Indeed, recordings of live performances that emphasize electronic effects, including reliance on electronic amplification, electronic instruments allowing special effects such as wah-wah produced by a supplementary foot-operated pedal, and so on, suggest the goal is that of emulating a recording as nearly as possible, which is quite different from the sonic ideals of live performance in the acoustic vein.

The case of covers—that is, playings of previously recorded songs—has implications for musical ontology. Often, tribute bands produce covers (usually as live performances rather than recordings) that try to match the original recording as closely as possible. The work they target is the thick piece for playback. But other artists treat the songs they cover in ways that are very different from the original. Joe Cocker’s live Woodstock version of the Beatles’ “With a Little Help from my Friends” is famously divergent in style, instrumentation, and length from the original. Here, the work that is targeted is the thin song. The thin song is what is (roughly) represented on sheet music and it lends itself to wide interpretation, whether given live or recorded. This brings out the fact that the original recording simultaneously manifests two works. Usually, the primary object of appreciation is the thick recording, in all its detail, but underneath lies a barebones song that can be taken up and interpreted by others (Gracyk 1996; Fisher 1998). (For more on covers, see Gracyk 2012–13; Magnus, Magnus, and Mag Uidhir 2013; Rings 2013, 2014; and Brown 2014.)

This takes us to the second kind of musical work: those for live performance. Prior to the late-nineteenth century, hearing the vast majority of musical works involved being within earshot of a live-playing event. Works for performance are better compared to plays for acting than to movies, both with respect to how they instance the work and to the interpretative freedom they display from rendition to rendition.

It is not necessary that all the parts or elements of a work for performance are for live playing. In some compositions, a tape or recording is included. Examples are Edgard Varèse’s Déserts with its recording of factory sounds, and Ottorino Respighi’s Pines of Rome with its recording of the song of a nightingale.

Just as there can be more than one version of a work for playback, there can be more than one version of a work for live performance (S. Davies 2007; Puy 2019). This occurs when a finished piece in the public domain is changed in ways that alter its identity and then re-released by its composer. For example, more than thirty years after it was composed, Stravinsky re-orchestrated Petrushka (Wachtel 1998) and Bruckner frequently revised his completed and published symphonies, often years after they had first been written (Horton 2004). To avoid confusion, versions can be time-indexed: for example, the 1887 version of Quartet No. 2. (On who may be authorized to change a work, see Friedell 2018.)

How are works for live performance specified? In oral traditions, they come into the world via exemplars and direct instruction (in which, for instance, each musician is taught their specific part). Sometimes a sketchy notation serves as a mnemonic aid. Though they rely on memory, there can be large repertoires of works in oral traditions and, as was explained earlier, individual pieces can be both extended and complex.

The philosopher David Davies has suggested that works introduced via exemplars, such as novels, allow no room for variability in their instances (D. Davies 2018). But this is plainly false in the case of musical works in an oral tradition (S. Davies 2001). For example, the Balinese piece “Teruna jaya” mentioned earlier exists in multiple variants. There can be difficulties in separating work-constitutive elements from performance-interpretative features within the exemplar, but shared conventions for the kind of music in question plus repeated presentations of the exemplar by custodians of its identity clarify this distinction. As a result, performers learn what is mandatory and what is variable in the exemplars on which they base their performances.

Many cultures have developed notations for the specification of works. The composers and musicians who employ them must be familiar with the conventions for reading them (S. Davies 2001; see also Nannicelli 2011); they are not always literal and sometimes they include indications that are not work-mandatory. As well, some work-mandatory elements may be absent, being assumed rather than notated. This is often the case with expected embellishments and decorations (S. Davies 1987, 1988; see also Young 1988). The function of specifying works is usually primary, but music notations can have other purposes as was observed earlier (e.g., as a mnemonic device, a transcription of a piece or its performance, or a retrospective indication of the thin song at the heart of a recorded pop piece).

Notational work-specifications underdetermine the sound of a performance, no matter how detailed they are. This is where the space for the performer’s interpretation lies. Even where something is instructed, many subtle aspects of its realization are left to the performer. They shape the melodic phrase, using micro-deviations from strict tempo, for instance. We value performances not solely for the works they display but also for their interpretative richness and for the light shed on the work by performance interpretations. Diverse performances, each equally and maximally faithful to the work, can differ in their interpretations. (For further discussion of performance interpretation, see S. Davies 1987, 2001, 2002; Godlovitch 1988; Young 1988; Levinson 1993; Kivy 1995; Thom 2003, 2007; D. Davies 2011; and Neufeld 2011.)

As just implied, performances of works invite questions about their authenticity. Almost always, faithfulness to the work will be a performance virtue (S. Davies 1987, 2001) and the more so where works are sufficiently complex and detailed to be valuable in their own right. Here, faithfulness is understood as accurately following what the score, appropriately interpreted, instructs as work-determinative. (For different views, see Dipert 1993, Kivy 1995, and Dodd 2015.) More particularly, where the works are old, they should be played on the kinds of instruments for which they were written and in the style of the time, and with notation interpreted according to the conventions of the day. The idea is that, because composers knew what they were doing, showing the work in the best light is most likely achieved by doing what the composer wanted. Moreover, if public performers represent their playing as of the given work, then they should accept a prima facie obligation to deliver that work as specified.

This said, qualifications are in order. Practical constraints might dictate departures from authenticity if a work is to be played at all. Perhaps the instruments are not available or no one knows how to play them. (For example, the ancient circular trumpets called for in Respighi’s Pines of Rome are usually now replaced by flugelhorns.) As well, other kinds of virtues of performances—dynamism, excitement, novelty—can be in tension with authenticity, at least when it is pursued formulaically. And, as we know from performances shot through with wrong or out-of-tune notes, works can remain recognizable in very inaccurate performances, so a degree of deliberate inauthenticity can be consistent with the intention to play the work in question. In practice, however, intended departures from authenticity are usually on the modest end of the scale, at least in the rendition of Western classical music, or are advertised in advance when professional musicians play to a paying public.

What are we to make of recordings of works intended for live performance? It is important to note these stay close to the conventions for live performance, at least for the case of Western classical music. Multiple takes and editing are likely to be used to eliminate errors and infelicities that will stand out uncomfortably in a recording intended to be listened to often, but long takes and the avoidance of studio manipulations are the norm (Godlovitch 1988; S. Davies 2001). Typically, it is assumed the musicians could play the relevant pieces in real time in live performance, and most ensembles that record also play the same music live.

Where the tradition is performance-based rather than work-based, as in jazz, the norms for recordings can differ. For instance, the musicians might record many takes and stop only when each of them is satisfied with the result. But again, it is generally assumed that the musicians could play a live rendition displaying similar improvisatory skills to those found on the record.

Risky or deliberately strange interpretations are less common in recordings than in live performances, presumably for commercial reasons. At the same time, the intimacy of recorded music mitigates the need to project to the far corners of an auditorium and encourages a more fastidious, subtle style of interpretation. A few performers, the pianist Glenn Gould being the obvious example, have preferred the distinctive circumstances of the recording studio for the display of their performances.

Ontological Theories of Musical Works

Musical works for playback, not performance, should be similar in their ontology to movies, photographic and other kinds of prints, cast statues, and the like. All these are based on a master or template, their instances are (potentially) multiple, and there is a high degree of resemblance between their various instances as a result of high transmissibility between the template and its decodings. In the musical case (and in movies and photography) lies an intermediate phase where the template gives rise to multiple, similar encodings (e.g., disks, copied files, pianola rolls) and the instances are generated from these, not directly from the original template.

The ontology of musical works for playback has not attracted much attention from analytic philosophers, apart from considering what is the primary object of appreciation in rock, as discussed earlier. I take it this is because the familiar type-token model (Wollheim 1968) fits the case unproblematically. (The same might apply to works of sound art, which have not been discussed here; see Hamilton 2007 and Pardo 2017.) The idea is that the tokens all resemble the type, what was referred to earlier as the template, in its crucial features. In the case of the Union Jack, the type is the pattern of forms and colors and the tokens are the individual flags that share the relevant design.

The main philosophical focus has been on works for live performance, and these have been analyzed in ontologically diverse terms.

The Platonist regards musical works as abstract, eternal patterns of sounds discovered by composers; the name derives from Plato’s theory, according to which actual things are imperfect copies of eternal forms they exemplify. Platonists include Kivy (1983, 1987) and Dodd (2000, 2002, 2007, 2008, 2010, 2012); see also Price (1982) and Scruton (1997). To detach works further from their real-world performances, the philosopher of music Peter Kivy regards them as timbreless (see also Webster 1974): a Beethoven symphony could be authentically rendered by a choir of kazoos. Another philosopher, Julian Dodd, thinks timbre is work-constitutive but the use of the specified instrument to produce that sound is irrelevant (see also Scruton 1997). He requires the violin concerto have the sound as of a violin, but it need not be played by a violin (Dodd 2007). I have called this position timbral sonicism (S. Davies 2001, 64–5).

Platonists are aware of how their views can appear to be counterintuitive and defend against this. For instance, Kivy, who thinks musical works are discovered, not created, argues only a particular person at a particular place and time could have made the relevant discovery (Kivy 1983, 1987). Against this, critics have argued musical works are created, not discovered, or how we talk of works involve commitments to creation contrary to discovery. (For discussions favoring the view musical works are created, not discovered, see Levinson 1980, 1990a; Thom 1990; Fisher 1991; Sharpe 1995, 2001; Predelli 2001; Trivedi 2002; Caplan and Matheson 2004; and Cameron 2008.) Indeed, it has been argued some types, including musical works, can be created via acts of indication, selection, initiation, or stipulation (Wolterstorff 1975, 1980; Levinson 1980, 1990a; Deutsch 1991; Howell 2002; Walters 2013). Meanwhile, it has been suggested the work’s instrumentation (often) contributes to its identity and therefore, works must be played on the appropriate kinds of instruments if the performance is to be faithful to the work (Levinson 1980, 1990a, 1990b; S. Davies 1987, 2001, 2008; Walton 1988; Bender 1993). (For further discussion and objections to Platonism, see Khatchadourian 1973, 1978; Sharpe 1995; Predelli 2002, 2006; Nussbaum 2003; Alward 2004; Kania 2008d, 2012b; Trivedi 2008; D. Davies 2009, 2018; Ridley 2012; Letts 2015, 2018; and Killin 2017.)

An alternative to Platonism construes musical works (or at least, those for live performance) as classes or sets of performances (Rudner 1950; Beardsley 1958; Goodman 1968; Bachrach 1971). This was sometimes presented as an eliminativist position. There are no musical works as such; phrases such as “Beethoven’s Fifth Symphony” are non-referring and we would do better to renounce all talk of musical works.

Fictionalism is similar, though it regards talk of musical works as useful and worth preserving because it makes some ways of discussing performances easier. (Fictionalists about musical works include Kania 2008c, 2012b; Killin 2017. For critical discussion of Kania’s position, see Letts 2015.) On this view, our apparent references to musical works treat them as convenient fictions. This discourse is useful, fictionalist argue, because it directs us to performance practices and ways of thinking of the underlying goals of performances that are of value. Discussing the virtues of this approach, philosopher Anton Killin explains:

Fictionalism is a theory by which one can disclaim unwanted ontological commitments to suspicious or dubious entities, whilst reaping some of the benefits of those very commitments, not through paraphrase but by putting forward statements in a fictionalistic light. So as long as the fictionalist has a claim to the fiction’s utility, fictionalism is having one’s cake and eating it too. (Killin 2017, 275)

Problems faced by eliminativism and fictionalism include explaining how we group performances into the relevant classes or sets (especially if some performances are less than well-formed), showing that the attributes of classes or sets can match those we ascribe to works, and accounting for the importance we attach to the role played by composers. (For further criticism, see D. Davies 2009; Predelli 2009; Letts 2015.)

Another recently presented position construes works not as classes of performances but as fusions of performances (Caplan and Matheson 2006; Matheson and Caplan 2007; Tillman 2011; Tillman and Spencer 2012; Aliyev 2017). Some versions of this view count only fully faithful performances, while others include scores and recordings in addition. This kind of theory takes musical works to be concrete existents (made up of performances or of performances plus scores and recordings). Musical works can be created, interacted with, and heard (while abstracta cannot be). Advocates have addressed many of the obvious issues with this position: performances are intermittent (whereas the work persists), can be simultaneous (i.e., the work can be spatially scattered), can contain wrong notes, and also a work could have had more or fewer performances.

A similar position is works are continuants that depend on performances and the like without being constituted by them (Rohrbaugh 2003). And another related position is works are complex events consisting of networks of causally-related performances (Alward 2004).

The idea that musical works are fusions of performances comes in two versions, according to the account of work-persistence adopted. If the work endures, it is entirely present at all times after its creation (Tillman 2011); whereas if it perdures, it exists only at the times it is being performed (Caplan and Matheson 2006; Tillman and Spencer 2012). An alternative account of persistence yields a contrasting thesis in which, rather than being fusions of performances, musical works are spatio-temporal stages mapped by performances (Moruzzi 2018; see also Edidin 1997). Here the musical work is a stage/performance connected by a privileged relationship (repeatability) to other stages/performances.

These last several theories have in common that they are all transferred from the literature on the ontology of material objects and, more specifically, on personal identity and are then applied to musical works. With that in mind, we should perhaps focus on ways in which musical works and people are obviously different. People exist continuously (unless they are treated as purely mental and then disappear when asleep), whereas the existence of musical works is very gappy (unless one subscribes to endurantism). As well, the same work can be performed at the same time in different places, whereas (short of time travel or science fictions in which people are cloned) people are not multiple in equivalent ways. And under some conditions, more than one musical work can be present in a single performance event (S. Davies 2001, 175–81), as when Tchaikovsky’s 1812 Overture contains “La Marseillaise,” whereas the presence of one person at a time and place is thought usually to exclude the presence of others.

Moreover, we should expect the score or exemplar to play a significant role in explaining the repeatability of musical works; however, people have no equivalent of a score-role or of stages that are special in being exemplary. Of course, ontologists might not see these differences as significant and there are ways of tackling some of them (Caplan and Matheson 2006). In my view, it is far from intuitively obvious that notions of identity that might work for people are likely to transfer successfully to musical works. (For further critical discussion, see Dodd 2007, Kania 2008d, and D. Davies 2018.)

I turn now to Levinson’s account, with which I am generally sympathetic. At first, he suggests that a musical work is a “sound/performing means structure,” (that is, the combination of a structure of notes with the specific instrumental means by which it is to be realized) as “indicated” by a composer at a given time (Levinson 1980, 486). Later he replaces “sound/performance means structure” with “performed sound structure” on the grounds that the former wrongly implies both two antecedently-specified things (sound structures and performing means structures) are brought into conjunction and the performing means structure (the instrumentation) has the same reality and importance as the sound structure (the notes) (Levinson 1990a, 261). Following a suggestion from James C. Anderson (1985), Levinson changes the imprecise “indicates” to “makes normative” (Levinson 1990a, 260), which indicates that the composer is directing potential performers of their work.

The reference to indication (or making normative) was to explain how the sound sequence is pulled, so to speak, from the world of abstracta into the actual, temporal world where it was then tethered to concreta such as the composer and performance means. But the vagueness of this notion has been criticized (Thom 1990; Bender 1993; Alward 2004; Evnine 2009). It seems to me Levinson provides no way to distinguish work-specifying prescriptive acts of indication made in the role of composer from others that are not work-identifying made by the same person in the role of performer or conductor (S. Davies 2001). The story of work indication has to consider musical practices and conventions governing the finalization of the work’s compositions absent from Levinson’s account, rather than presenting this as a simple act of fiat. (For discussion of how these conventions sometimes go awry or are flouted, see S. Davies 2007.)

Levinson does not rely solely on indicating or making normative to connect the work’s sound sequence to concrete, real features of the world. He follows an argument used against traditional aesthetic accounts of art. This argument tries to show that lookalike artworks—perceptually and hence aesthetically identical—can have different, artistically significant properties as a result of the context in and intentions with which they are made and presented (Danto 1964; Walton 1970). In this vein, Levinson argues works could share the same sound structure and yet differ in their identities thanks to their context (Levinson 1980; see also Currie 1988). Levinson provides examples of aesthetically-significant properties affected both by the general musico-historical setting and by the composer’s individual situation. Arnold Schoenberg’s Pierrot Lunaire, Op. 21 (1912) would have been yet more anguished if it had been composed (at the same time) by Richard Strauss. Whereas Mendelssohn’s style was original, someone writing in the same style in 1900 would not be. A work could be Liszt-influenced only if written after the relevant compositions of Liszt. Johann Stamitz’s Mannheim rockets (a musical gesture in which an ascending rapid scale or arpeggio was coupled with a crescendo) were exciting in the mid-eighteenth century but quaint and funny in works of more recent times. Bartók could not have been satirizing Dmitri Shostakovich’s Symphony No. 7 (1941), known as the “Leningrad,” in his Concerto for Orchestra (1945) if it had been written in 1939.

As well, a composer’s work should properly be heard in relation to their other compositions and would differ in artistic properties if their prior compositions had been different (even if the notes remained the same). Levinson (1990a, 1990b) defends these examples, which are supposed to establish that the composer’s identity and the work’s means of performance are crucial to its identity, against criticisms presented by Kivy (1988) and others.

I share Levinson’s commitment to ontological contextualism (S. Davies 2001, 72–86; see also Gracyk 2009), which is the idea that a work’s musico-historical context can affect its properties, including (sometimes) ones relevant to its identity as the work it is (S. Davies 1994a, 1994b). Its relations to styles, genres, period, repertoire, tradition, and composer’s oeuvre could all affect the identity of a given composition. That is, the musico-cultural setting at the time of the work’s composition might contribute, along with its sound structure, to its being the work it is. (I do not agree that the work’s reception, after it has been created, can alter its identity, however. Compare with Matheson and Caplan 2007: Its significance and social context can change, but not its identity.)

Despite holding this view, I do not follow Levinson in regarding its instrumentation as always among a musical work’s identifying features, as should be apparent from the discussion of instrumentation earlier. The substitution of an oboe for the clarinet, where none is available, will surely alter some of the work’s aesthetic or artistic features, but whether this amounts to a departure from the work’s identity depends on the wider context. Even if Mozart preferred the clarinet, it is not plain that he could mandate its inclusion in his Symphony No. 39, K 543 of 1788 (S. Davies 2001, 67–8), though Brahms’ adoption of the instrument in a later period makes it a requirement. It is the musical practice of the surrounding context that decides, in the end, when a composer’s work-identifying wishes become work-specifications. And as regards instrumentation, it was practical, contingent aspects of musical practice—the standardization of instrument types and uniformity in the make-up of the orchestra, alongside the reasonable expectation of high standards of professional musicianship—that, over time, turned the choice of instrumentation from a performance-interpretative option into a work-identifying requirement. Of course, the resulting loss of performance flexibility (for the performers) was far outweighed by the expressive and textural nuance that then could be achieved (by the composer).

Let me contrast my response to Levinson with one proposed by Henry Deutsch I have only recently encountered. Deutsch objects to Levinson’s different-works-with-same-sound-structure arguments: “First, it is both possible and natural to interpret the examples [those listed above, such as Richard Strauss’s doppelganger composition of Pierrot Lunaire] as showing at most only that the same work can have different aesthetic or artistic attributes in different contexts” (Deutsch 1991, 214). I agree, if not with respect to all of Levinson’s examples but at least in relation to the issues about instrumentation just mentioned. But Deutsch adds further criticisms I do not agree with:

Secondly, in drawing this conclusion, Levinson is endorsing an extreme and highly improbable version of the doctrine that to fully comprehend and appreciate a work of art one must be intimately acquainted with the personal, historical, and cultural facts surrounding its creation. It is Levinson’s view that not only is such information relevant to appreciating the aesthetic qualities of work, it may also be required in order to know what work is being performed—even in the rudimentary sense of being able to recognize the work on hearing it for the second, third, or nth time. (Deutsch 1991, 214)

In fact, I do think that the fullest appreciation of any work is likely to require information about the composer, his oeuvre, the wider musical context, and so on. But I do not see why identifying the work as such needs detailed awareness of every work-constituting feature. If we can recognize works in performances riddled with wrong notes then we can surely recognize them on the basis of their sound structure alone, even if the work’s identity takes in more than this. Deutsch arrives at this point:

If the “Leningrad” had not appeared before the time Bartok wrote the Concerto for Orchestra, the latter could not bear any but an adventitious relation to the former. It doesn’t follow that the latter wouldn’t be the Concerto for Orchestra. (Deutsch 1991, 215)

I agree this conclusion is not strictly entailed by Levinson’s argument, but at this stage I would defend Levinson’s view by appealing to how the work is to be appreciated. Is Bartok’s mocking allusion to the banality of Shostakovich’s melody a factor in his Concerto’s identity? So prominent is the passage and so stylistically anomalous is it in the piece’s wider context that it would not make musical sense except as a reference; thus, there is good reason to doubt we should consider the identical, hypothetical pre-“Leningrad” and actual post-“Leningrad” Bartok compositions as one and the same. If it is true that without The Odyssey, James Joyce’s Ulysses is impossible (as maintained in Rohrbaugh 2005, 216), then it looks as if we can equally say: Without the “Leningrad,” Bartok’s Concerto for Orchestra is impossible.

Levinson’s examples are also supposed to justify his tethering the work’s identity to that of its composer. Again, I have disagreed. Two composers with very different styles or working in historically separated musical traditions and contexts would produce different works, even if those works shared the same sound structure. That is because the two works would have very different artistic properties relative to their context of origin. But two composers sharing very similar styles and working in a shared musical culture might independently write the same, single work. In this regard, I compared the young Mozart to one of J. S. Bach’s sons, Johann Christian Bach (S. Davies 2001, 83). If experts could not decide which of them composed a given piece, then either of them could have and, despite the statistical improbability, both of them might have done so independently. In this latter case, it would be reasonable to conclude that only one work, not two, had been composed. This conclusion was anticipated by Deutsch:

The examples Levinson gives suggest at most that works with the same sound structure would nonetheless appear to have different properties when viewed as situated in widely different musico-historical contexts. This does not imply that two composers could not produce the same work within virtually the same musico-historical context. (Deutsch 1991, 214)

Here it helps to distinguish what philosopher Guy Rohrbaugh (2005) calls the “individuation question” (i.e., could the work have been written by someone else in this world?) from the “modal question” about the necessity of authorship (i.e., could the work have been written by someone else in a possible world?). Rohrbaugh defends the essentiality of authorship for most works of art but regards Levinson’s treatment, which takes the individuation question to be associated with the modal one, to be unsupported: “An ontological theory that provided fine individuation of works but allowed authorship to vary counterfactually would be equally supported” (Rohrbaugh 2005, 214).

Meanwhile, Robert Stecker thinks modal intuitions about musical works are liable to vary, thus arguments that appeal to them are indecisive; musical works “cannot change in the way physical objects…do, and it is not clear that they ever undergo a change in intrinsic properties. So, there are fewer opportunities for counterfactual thoughts about musical works to have a natural home” (Stecker 2009, 375–6). By way of illustrating the clash of intuitions, Stecker cites the dispute between Levinson (1980) and Gregory Currie (1988) over whether the composer’s identity contributes to the musical work’s identity.

My View

In my view, composers do not indicate sound structures; instead, they design them. I’m not bothered whether this is described as creation or discovery, though I lean toward the former and stress if discovery is instead to be the preferred option, what is involved is a very active pursuit of the target discovered. This process of design involves discriminating between many similar sound structures and includes bringing possibilities for sound structures into conversation with musical practices and traditions: repertoire, oeuvre, genre, styles (personal and general), instruments and performance practices, and notational conventions. The relations in which the composer’s specification stands to these matters that lie beyond the work’s boundaries affect the work’s contents and, in some cases, its identity-conferring features. To take just one obvious example, musical works often quote, allude to, pay homage to, or are influenced by other musical works, styles, or genres. This can be relevant to their being the works they are. The work is not some abstract thing but, rather, a complex generated out of real-world relations and instructions. Musical works (for performance) are communicated through instructions addressed to performers. The injunction is: If you would play my work, do thus and so. “Thus and so” presupposes and makes sense only against the background of performance practice, instrumental options, notational conventions, and so on.

A simple analogy might make matters clearer. Knitting patterns are instructions for the making of such items as sweaters. Sweaters, and the designs they instantiate, include patterns but are not abstracta. A sweater design (such as Fair Isle) might be presented by appropriate instructions or via an exemplar. Typical knitting patterns include symbols such as:

: (blank) knit stitch (K) on right side; purl on wrong side
: purl (P) on right side; knit on wrong side
o: yarn over (YO)
\: slip, slip, knit (ssk) on right side; slip, slip, purl (ssp) on wrong side
/: knit 2 together (k2tog) on right side; purl 2 together (p2tog) on wrong side

To execute such instructions, the knitter needs to know what knit and purl stitches are, which side is right and which wrong, and so on. Such instructions make sense only against the background of a clothing world, practices of ornamentation, wool production and dyeing, technical notions such as crimp and yarn, different gauges and types of needles, and so on. The pattern might leave color choice entirely to the knitter, or might offer non-mandatory recommendations about this, or might specify color details precisely and in the expectation they will be followed. Typically, the pattern can be altered to accommodate such local factors as the size of the intended wearer. Because they are so heavily linked to the practices and practicalities that give point to their existence, it would be silly to think of specific sweater designs as abstract eternalities.

ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS

For their comments on drafts I thank Peter Alward, Julian Dodd, John Fisher, Ted Gracyk, Andrew Kania, and Matteo Ravasio.

WORKS CITED

Aliyev, Alexey. 2017. “Musical Perdurantism and the Problem of Intermittent Existence.” Grazer Philosophische Studien 94 (1-2): 83–100.

Alward, Peter. 2004. “The Spoken Work.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 62 (4): 331–7.

Anderson, James C. 1985. “Musical Kinds.” British Journal of Aesthetics 25 (1): 43–9.

Apel, Willi. 1958. Gregorian Chant. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

Bachrach, Jay. 1971. “Type and Token and the Identification of the Work of Art.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 31 (3): 415–20.

Bartel, Christopher. 2011. “Music without Metaphysics.” British Journal of Aesthetics 51 (4): 383–98.

Bartel, Christopher. 2017. “Rock as a Three-Value Tradition.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 75 (2): 143–54.

Baugh, Bruce. 1993. “Prolegomena to Any Aesthetics of Rock Music.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 51 (1): 23–9.

Beardsley, Monroe C. 1958. Aesthetics: Problems in the Philosophy of Criticism. New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World.

Bender, John W. 1993. “Music and Metaphysics: Types and Patterns, Performances and Works.” In Contemporary Philosophy of Art: Readings in Analytic Aesthetics, edited by J. W. Bender and H. G. Blocker, 354–65. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.

Brown, Lee B. 2011. “Do Higher-Order Music Ontologies Rest on a Mistake?” British Journal of Aesthetics 51 (2): 169–84.

Brown, Lee B. 2012. “Further Doubts about Higher-Order Ontology: Reply to Andrew Kania.” British Journal of Aesthetics 52 (1): 103–6.

Brown, Lee B. 2014. “A Critique of Michael Rings on Covers.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 72 (2): 193–5.

Brown, Lee B., David Goldblatt, and Theodore Gracyk. 2018. Jazz and the Philosophy of Art. New York: Routledge.

Bruno, Franklin. 2013. “A Case for Song: Against an (Exclusively) Recording-Centered Ontology of Rock.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 71 (1): 65–74.

Burkett, Dan. 2015. “One Song, Many Works: A Pluralist Ontology of Rock.” Contemporary Aesthetics 13. https://contempaesthetics.org/newvolume/pages/article.php?articleID=722

Cameron, Ross P. 2008. “There Are No Things That Are Musical Works.” British Journal of Aesthetics 48 (3): 295–314.

Caplan, Ben, and Carl Matheson. 2004. “Can a Musical Work Be Created?” British Journal of Aesthetics 44 (2): 113–34.

Caplan, Ben, and Carl Matheson. 2006. “Defending Musical Perdurantism.” British Journal of Aesthetics 46 (1): 59–69.

Carpenter, Patricia. 1967. “The Musical Object.” Current Musicology 5: 56–87.

Cray, Wesley D., and Carl Matheson. 2017. “A Return to Musical Idealism.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 95 (4): 702–15.

Currie, Gregory. 1988. An Ontology of Art. London: Macmillan.

Danto, Arthur C. 1964. “The Artworld.” Journal of Philosophy 61 (19): 571–84.

Davies, David. 2003. Art as Performance. Malden: Blackwell.

Davies, David. 2009. “Dodd on the ‘Audibility’ of Musical Works.” British Journal of Aesthetics 49 (2): 99–108.

Davies, David. 2011. Philosophy of the Performing Arts. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.

Davies, David. 2017. “Descriptivism and Its Discontents.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 75 (2): 117–129.

Davies, David. 2018. “Locating the Performable Musical Work in Practice: A Non-Platonist Interpretation of the ‘Classical Paradigm’.” In Virtual Works–Actual Things: Essays in Music Ontology, edited by Paulo de Assis, 45–64. Leuven: Leuven University Press.

Davies, Stephen. 1987. “Authenticity in Musical Performance.” British Journal of Aesthetics 27 (1): 39–50.

Davies, Stephen. 1988. “Authenticity in Performance: A Reply to James O. Young.” British Journal of Aesthetics 28 (4): 373–76.

Davies, Stephen. 1991. “The Ontology of Musical Works and the Authenticity of their Performances.” Noûs 25 (1): 21–41.

Davies, Stephen. 1994a. Musical Meaning and Expression. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

Davies, Stephen. 1994b. “Musical Understanding and Musical Kinds.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 52 (1): 69–81.

Davies, Stephen. 2001. Musical Works and Performances: A Philosophical Exploration. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Davies, Stephen. 2002. “The Multiple Interpretability of Musical Works.” In Is There a Single Right Interpretation? Edited by M. Krausz, 231–50. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.

Davies, Stephen. 2003. “Ontologies of Musical Works.” In Themes in the Philosophy of Music, 30–46. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Davies, Stephen. 2007. “Versions of Musical Works and Literary Translations.” In Philosophers on Music: Experience, Meaning, and Work, edited by K. Stock, 79–92. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Davies, Stephen. 2008. “Musical Works and Orchestral Colour.” British Journal of Aesthetics 48 (4): 363–75.

Deutsch, Henry. 1991. “The Creation Problem.” Topoi 10 (2): 209–25.

Dipert, Randall R. 1993. Artifacts, Art Works, and Agency. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

Dodd, Julian. 2000. “Musical Works as Eternal Types.” British Journal of Aesthetics 40 (4): 424–40.

Dodd, Julian. 2002. “Defending Musical Platonism.” British Journal of Aesthetics 42 (4): 380–402.

Dodd, Julian. 2007. Works of Music: An Essay in Ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Dodd, Julian. 2008. “Musical Works: Ontology and Meta-Ontology.” Philosophy Compass 3 (6): 1113–34.

Dodd, Julian. 2010. “Confessions of an Unrepentant Timbral Sonicist.” British Journal of Aesthetics 50 (1): 33–52.

Dodd, Julian. 2012. “Defending the Discovery Model in the Ontology of Art: A Reply to Amie Thomasson on the Qua Problem.” British Journal of Aesthetics 52 (1): 75–95.

Dodd, Julian. 2013. “Adventures in the Metaontology of Art: Local Descriptivism, Artefacts, and Dreamcatchers.” Philosophical Studies 165 (3): 1047–68.

Dodd, Julian. 2014. “Upholding Standards: A Realist Ontology of Standard Form Jazz.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 72 (3): 277–90.

Dodd, Julian. 2015. “Performing Works of Music Authentically.” European Journal of Philosophy 23 (3): 485–508.

Edidin, Aron. 1997. “Performing Compositions.” British Journal of Aesthetics 37 (4): 323–35.

Edlund, Bengt. 1996. “On Scores and Works of Music: Interpretation and Identity.” British Journal of Aesthetics 36 (4): 367–80.

Evnine, Simon J. 2009. “Constitution and Qua Objects in the Ontology of Music.” British Journal of Aesthetics 49 (3): 203–17.

Fisher, John Andrew. 1991. “Discovery, Creation, and Musical Works.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 49 (2): 129–36.

Fisher, John Andrew. 1998. “Rock ‘n’ Recording: The Ontological Complexity of Rock Music.” In Musical Worlds: New Directions in the Philosophy of Music, edited by P. Alperson, 109–23. University Park: The Pennsylvania State University Press.

Fisher, John Andrew. 2018. “Jazz and Musical Works: Hypnotized by the Wrong Model.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 76 (2): 151–62.

Friedell, David. 2018. “Why Can’t I Change Bruckner’s Eighth Symphony?” Philosophical Studies 177 (3): 805–824. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1207-3

Godlovitch, Stan. 1988. Musical Performance: A Philosophical Study. London: Routledge.

Goehr, Lydia. 1992. The Imaginary Museum of Musical Works: An Essay in the Philosophy of Music. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Goodman, Nelson. 1968. Languages of Art. New York: Bobbs-Merrill.

Gracyk, Theodore A. 1996. Rhythm and Noise: An Aesthetics of Rock Music. Durham: Duke University Press.

Gracyk, Theodore A. 2009. “Ontological Contextualism.” In A Companion to Aesthetics, edited by S. Davies, K. M. Higgins, R. Hopkins, R. Stecker, and D. E. Cooper, 449–53. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.

Gracyk, Theodore A. 2012–2013. “Covers and Communicative Intentions.” Journal of Music and Meaning 11: 22–46.

Grout, Donald Jay. 2010. A History of Western Music. 8th ed. New York: W. W. Norton.

Hamilton, Andy. 2007. Aesthetics and Music. London: Continuum.

Horton, Julian. 2004. Bruckner’s Symphonies: Analysis, Reception and Cultural Politics. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Howell, Robert. 2002. “Types, Indicated and Initiated.” British Journal of Aesthetics 42 (2): 105–27.

Ingarden, Roman. 1986. The Work of Music and the Problem of Its Identity. Translated by A. Czerniawski. Berkeley: University of California Press.

Kania, Andrew. 2006. “Making Tracks: The Ontology of Rock Music.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 64 (4): 401–14.

Kania, Andrew. 2008a. “Works, Recordings, Performances: Classical, Rock, Jazz.” In Recorded Music: Philosophical and Critical Reflections, edited by M. Dogantan-Dack, 3–21. Hendon: Middlesex University Press.

Kania, Andrew. 2008b. “Piece for the End of Time: In Defence of Musical Ontology.” British Journal of Aesthetics 48 (1): 65–79.

Kania, Andrew. 2008c. “The Methodology of Musical Ontology: Descriptivism and Its Implications.” British Journal of Aesthetics 48 (4): 426–44.

Kania, Andrew. 2008d. “New Waves in Musical Ontology.” In New Waves in Aesthetics, edited by K. Stock and K. Thomson-Jones, 21–40. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

Kania, Andrew. 2011. “All Play and No Work: An Ontology of Jazz.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 69 (4): 391–403.

Kania, Andrew. 2012a. “In Defence of Higher-Order Musical Ontology: A Reply to Lee B. Brown.” British Journal of Aesthetics 52 (1): 97–102.

Kania, Andrew. 2012b. “Platonism vs. Nominalism in Contemporary Musical Ontology.” In Art and Abstract Objects, edited by C. Mag Uidhir, 197–219. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Khatchadourian, Haig. 1973. “The Identity of a Work of Music.” Music and Man 1 (1): 33–57.

Khatchadourian, Haig. 1978. “The Identity of a Work of Music – II.” Music and Man 2 (3-4): 223–33.

Killin, Anton. 2017. “Fictionalism about Musical Works.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 48 (2): 266–91.

Kivy, Peter. 1983. “Platonism in Music.” Grazer Philosophische Studien 19 (1): 109–29.

Kivy, Peter. 1987. “Platonism in Music: Another Kind of Defense.” American Philosophical Quarterly 24 (3): 245–52.

Kivy, Peter. 1988. “Orchestrating Platonism.” In Aesthetic Distinction, edited by T. Anderberg, T. Nilstun, and I. Persson, 42–55. Lund: Lund University Press,

Kivy, Peter. 1995. Authenticities: Philosophical Reflections on Musical Performance. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

Kraut, Robert. 2012. “Ontology: Music and Art.” The Monist 95 (4): 684–710.

Letts, Philip. 2015. “Against Kania’s Fictionalism about Musical Works.” British Journal of Aesthetics 55 (2): 209–24.

Letts, Philip. 2018. “The Property Theory of Musical Works.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 76 (1): 57–69.

Levinson, Jerrold. 1980. “What a Musical Work Is.” Journal of Philosophy 77 (1): 5–28.

Levinson, Jerrold. 1990a. “What a Musical Work Is Again.” In Music, Art, and Metaphysics, 215–63. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

Levinson, Jerrold. 1990b. “Authentic Performance and Performance Means.” In Music, Art, and Metaphysics, 393–408. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

Levinson, Jerrold. 1993. “Performative versus Critical Interpretation in Music.” In The Interpretation of Music: Philosophical Essays, edited by M. Krausz, 33–60. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Luzio, Hugo. 2019. “The Ontology of Rock Music: Recordings, Performances and the Synthetic View.” Filozofija I drustvo 30 (1): 73–82.

Magnus, Cristyn, P. D. Magnus, and Christy Mag Uidhir. 2013. “Judging Covers.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 71 (4): 361–70.

Matheson, Carl, and Ben Caplan. 2007. “Fine Individuation.” British Journal of Aesthetics 47 (2): 113–37.

Moruzzi, Caterina. 2018. “Every Performance is a Stage: Musical Stage Theory as a Novel Account for the Ontology of Musical Works.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 76 (3): 341–51.

Nannicelli, Ted. 2011. “Instructions and Artworks: Musical Scores, Theatrical Scripts, Architectural Plans, and Screenplays.” British Journal of Aesthetics 51 (4): 399–414.

Neufeld, Jonathan A. 2011. “Living the Work: Meditations on a Lark.” Journal of Aesthetic Education 45 (1): 89–106.

Neufeld, Jonathan A. 2014. “Musical Ontology: Critical, not Metaphysical.” Contemporary Aesthetics 12. https://contempaesthetics.org/newvolume/pages/article.php?articleID=710&searchstr=neufeld

Nussbaum, Charles. 2003. “Kinds, Types, and Musical Ontology.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 61 (3): 273–91.

Pardo, Carmen. 2017. “The Emergence of Sound Art: Opening the Cages of Sound.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 75 (1): 35–48.

Predelli, Stefano. 1999. “Goodman and the Wrong Note Paradox.” British Journal of Aesthetics 39 (4): 364–75.

Predelli, Stefano. 2001. “Ontology and the Argument from Creation.” British Journal of Aesthetics 41 (3): 279–92.

Predelli, Stefano. 2002. “Has the Ontology of Music Rested on a Mistake?” Literature and Aesthetics 12: 1–19.

Predelli, Stefano. 2006. “Platonism in Music: A Kind of Refutation.” Revue Internationale de Philosophie 60 (4): 401–14.

Predelli, Stefano. 2009. “Ontologese and Musical Nihilism: A Reply to Cameron.” British Journal of Aesthetics 49 (2): 179–83.

Price, Kingsley. 1982. “What is a Piece of Music?” British Journal of Aesthetics 22 (4): 322–37.

Puy, Nemesio García-Carril. 2019. “The Ontology of Musical Versions: Introducing the Hypothesis of Nested Types.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 77 (3): 241–54.

Ridley, Aaron. 2003. “Against Musical Ontology.” Journal of Philosophy 100 (4): 203–20.

Ridley, Aaron. 2012. “Musical Ontology, Musical Reasons.” The Monist 95 (4): 663–83.

Rings, Michael. 2013. “Doing it Their Way: Rock Covers, Genres and Appreciation.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 71 (1): 55–63.

Rings, Michael. 2014. “Covers and (Mere?) Remakes: A Reply to Lee B. Brown.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 72 (2): 195–9.

Rohrbaugh, Guy. 2003. “Artworks as Historical Individuals.” European Journal of Philosophy 11 (2): 177–205.

Rohrbaugh, Guy. 2005. “I Could Have Done That.” British Journal of Aesthetics 45 (3): 209–28.

Rudner, Richard. 1950. “The Ontological Status of the Esthetic Object.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 10 (3): 380–8.

Scruton, Roger. 1997. The Aesthetics of Music. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Sharpe, R. A. 1995. “Music, Platonism and Performance: Some Ontological Strains.” British Journal of Aesthetics 35 (1): 38–48.

Sharpe, R. A. 2000. Music and Humanism: An Essay in the Aesthetics of Music. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Sharpe, R. A. 2001. “Could Beethoven have ‘Discovered’ the Archduke Trio?” British Journal of Aesthetics 41 (3): 325–27.

Stecker, Robert. 2009. “Methodological Questions about the Ontology of Music.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 67 (4): 375–86.

The Pianola Institute. 2019. http://www.pianola.org/history/history_stravinsky.cfm.

Thom, Paul. 1990. “Works for Performance.” Grazer Philosophische Studien 38 (1): 139–56.

Thom, Paul. 2003. For an Audience: A Philosophy of the Performing Arts. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

Thom, Paul. 2007. The Musician as Interpreter. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.

Thomasson, Amie L. 2005. “The Ontology of Art and Knowledge in Aesthetics.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 63 (3): 221–9.

Tillman, Chris, 2011. “Musical Materialism.” British Journal of Aesthetics 51 (1): 13–29.

Tillman, Chris, and Joshua Spencer. 2012. “Musical Materialism and the Inheritance Problem.” Analysis 72 (2): 252–9.

Trivedi, Saam. 2002. “Against Musical Works as Eternal Types.” British Journal of Aesthetics 42 (1): 73–82.

Trivedi, Saam. 2008. “Music and Metaphysics.” Metaphilosophy 39 (1): 124–43.

Wachtel, Andrew, ed. 1998. Petrushka: Sources and Contexts. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

Walters, Lee. 2013. “Artworks as Created Types.” British Journal of Aesthetics 53 (4): 461­–77.

Walton, Kendall L. 1970. “Categories of Art.” Philosophical Review 79 (3): 334–67.

Walton, Kendall L. 1988. “The Presentation and Portrayal of Sound Patterns.” In Human Agency: Language, Duty and Value, edited by J. Dancy, J.M.E. Moravcsik, and C.C.W. Taylor, 237–57. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

Webster, William E. 1974. “A Theory of the Compositional Work of Music.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 33 (1): 59–66.

Wollheim, Richard. 1968. Art and Its Objects. London: Pelican.

Wolterstorff, Nicholas. 1975. “Towards an Ontology of Artworks.” Noûs 9 (2): 115–42.

Wolterstorff, Nicholas. 1980. Works and Worlds of Art. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Young, James O. 1988. “The Concept of Authentic Performance.” British Journal of Aesthetics 28 (3): 228–38.

Young, James O. 2014/15. “The Poverty of Music Ontology.” Journal of Music and Meaning 13: 1–19.

Young, James O. and Carl Matheson. 2000. “The Metaphysics of Jazz.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 58 (2): 125–33.